eleven wrote:The strong links are there, if the puzzle has a solution or not.
Did you read a word I just said? Your statement is true if you're using mith's practical definition only. I was clearly speaking about the consequences of totuan's definition, which I consider the official one. Stick to that if you want to criticize what I wrote.
I definitely can use them to prove, that this puzzle has no solution, because applying them (correctly) leads to a contradiction.
Yeah, because your (like everyone else's) process looks like this:
1. Assume the puzzle has at least one solution.
2. Apply apparent strong links correctly, by mith's definition.
3. Arrive at a contradiction.
4. Conclude that that puzzle has no solution.
What you're missing is a fifth step based on that conclusion:
5. Conclude that the apparent strong links weren't real, by totuan's definition.
Which part do you disagree with?
--
Personally I think we need both definitions: one globally (totuan's) and the other locally (mith's).
The former is sufficient for puzzles that have at least one solution, because any valid strong link guarantees that at least one of the options is in a solution. It also provides the theoretical meaning for a strong link, and a quick way to prove one's invalidity if neither option is found in a solution.
However, the latter is what we all use in practice, and it's also necessary for when there is no solution (to prove that). Thus, in the no-solution context this is not exactly true:
SpAce wrote:That's the whole point of a strong link (or a larger SIS). If valid, it provides a 100% certainty that at least one of the options must be true in the solution, which gives it its solving power. If not valid, it can't prove anything. Any use of an invalid strong link amounts to guessing.
That global definition of validity only applies if there's at least one solution. In the no-solution context we must use a local definition (apparent validity), or otherwise we can't prove that there's no solution.